Is
it Already Time to Give Up on a Science of Consciousness? A Commentary
on Mysterianism
Giorgio
A. Ascoli, Krasnow Institute for Advanced Study at George Mason University,
MS2A1 - Fairfax, VA 22030-4444
Abstract:This
essay is an extended review of the book “The Mysterious Flame - Conscious
Minds in a Material World” by Colin McGinn. After a brief introduction,
the book is summarized. McGinn’s main thesis, that the problem of consciousness
cannot be solved scientifically because of an intrinsic limitation of the
human intellect, is then analyzed, particularly from the perspective of
modern neuroscience. I discuss the criticism of Materialism, which constitutes
a crucial part of the book, in light of the ideas of Churchland, Chalmers,
and others, and I review a finer distinction in the mind-body problem between
identity and causal relation. This leads to a discussion of the contribution
of Mysterianism to the ontology of scientific theories. Finally, I comment
on other critical passages of The Mysterious Flame and propose a
thought experiment to shed light on some of the issues raised in the book.
The
end of this millennium has seen the appearance of a plethora of books,
articles, reviews, conferences and workshops on “consciousness”. This movement
involves philosophers, but also psychologists, neurobiologists, physicists,
ethologists, mathematicians, computer scientists and thinkers from many
other disciplines. The participation of so many scientists in this debate
contrasts sharply with the traditional view that conscious experience cannot
be the object of scientific investigation because of its subjectivity,
privateness, and irreplicability. Certainly it is hard (if at all possible)
to approach matters such as qualia experimentally by the straightforward
“Galilean” method, and an adequate epistemology needs to be developed (see
e.g. [1]). One of the main reasons for the recent wealth of scientific
contributions to the consciousness debate is the fast progress of neurobiology,
brain imaging, and computer science. For example, recent discoveries concerning
the “code” of neural patterns, i.e. the characterization of the spatial
and temporal parameters by which neuronal activity represents, stores,
and transmits information, have brought the discussion of what “perception”
is to a more quantitative level than ever before [2-4]. The advancement
of techniques such as multi-electrode recording, functional imaging, emission
tomography, and magnetoencephalography (recently reviewed in [5-8], respectively)
carries the hope and the expectation that in a not-so-distant future we
will have a precise mapping of the neural correlates of any behavioral
or cognitive state, down to the system, cellular, and (in principle) sub-cellular
level. This new knowledge will integrate and complement the results obtained
through classical studies on pathological states such as blindsight and
split brains.
As
this progress promises to bring some fresh perspective in the age-old question
of the mind-body relationship, thinkers from different disciplines offer
a variety of views on the current status of a science of consciousness.
Opinions range from the statement that, as far as principles are concerned,
we already know what consciousness is and how it arises, while all that
is left to be discovered are details [9-11]; to a cautiously optimistic
prediction that the problem is hard indeed, but as science and technology
progresses, we will find the solution [12-14]; to the admission of the
possibility that currently available physical and biological concepts might
be unsuitable in and of themselves to tackle the problem, and that we should
find and introduce radically new ideas and tools in our search [15-17].
In this spectrum of positions, Colin McGinn stands at an extreme. In his
“mysterian” theory, he has argued for the cognitive closure of the
human mind: we will never really know what consciousness is and how it
arises, because the problem is beyond our intelligence. According to McGinn,
scientists should recognize that the brain is structurally not equipped
to “know” consciousness. Consequently, they should give up on trying to
address the scientific problem of consciousness, and leave it to philosophers
to mark the boundaries between what is in principle intelligible to humankind
and what is bound to remain a mystery forever.
In
The
Mysterious Flame – Conscious Minds in a Material World, McGinn reviews
the position of his mysterian thesis by collecting and summarizing themes
largely discussed in his previous books [18-21]. An important merit of
the current book is that it addresses the lay public. Philosophical jargon
and long, technical discussions of classical authors are kept to a minimum,
and arguments are usually accompanied by examples taken from everyday life,
or often, from the television series Star Trek. The attempt to reach
out to non-experts is praiseworthy, considering that consciousness can
be described as what all human beings have and no one can define. All people,
not just philosophers and scientists, should have access to the discussion
of what we mean by consciousness, and what the first-person experience
feels like. Unfortunately, however, The Mysterious Flame fundamentally
fails to support its core thesis with solid arguments, and several critical
passages are seriously flawed in ways I shall detail below.
The
book opens with a definition of consciousness encompassing basic phenomenological
experience, or the qualitative, subjective personal states usually referred
to as qualia. The author decides to leave out what he calls “reflective”
consciousness or self-awareness, reducing what he means by this term to
higher order internal representations (such as thinking of having a
sensation, emotion, feeling, or thought). The first chapter continues with
the programmatic statement that will be elaborated in the book, namely
that “the bond between the mind and the brain is a deep mystery, […] an
ultimate mystery that human intelligence will never unravel” (p. 5). In
order to delineate the terms mind and brain, McGinn reports
an extract from a sci-fi story, where aliens exploring the Earth remain
profoundly puzzled by how human beings can achieve consciousness with brain
made out of meat. The problem is restated as an invitation to the
reader to contemplate why (s)he should be conscious at all, while, say,
steaks are not. This introduction ends with a discussion of the two “orthodox
explanations” of consciousness, Materialism and Dualism, and why they “don’t
work” (p. 18). This part of the book is actually critically important to
the whole mysterian cause, as several subsequent chapters will crucially
refer to the flaws of Materialism and Dualism outlined here. McGinn’s arguments
against these two positions follow the classical philosophical debates:
it is hard to swallow that the mind is what the brain does, because the
first is subjective knowledge, the second is objective, and because the
two really feel different. And it seems quite difficult to maintain
that they are totally separate entities (which would also admit the possible
existence of zombies, ghosts, and the like) against increasingly solid
scientific and clinical evidence. After summarizing the remaining chapters,
I will return to McGinn’s attack on Materialism, as it raises major concerns
and affects much of the subsequent discussion.
The
second chapter constitutes the central logical justification of the mysterian
theory, and of the whole book. Here, all the evidence suggesting the unintelligibility
of consciousness is gathered, and the reader is invited to give up on a
deeper understanding. First, the author summarizes historical skeptical
positions (how do you know you are not living in a dream, or in virtual
reality?), and a series of questions which are impossible to answer are
offered as concrete examples (how many ants were there in Africa in the
year 1620?). Then he argues that the very structure of human intelligence
naturally allows certain capacities (e.g., language), but not others (e.g.,
echolocation), while other animals find themselves in different situations.
Given these circumstances, there is no reason, in principle, for theoretical
sciences to be limited to the human species. The reader is invited to imagine
an environment in which Evolution allowed the presence of species with
a wide range of cognitive capacities: some creatures would be remarkably
superior to humans in all aspects of scientific understanding, whereas
others would exceed us in only some aspects of scientific thought. This
exercise should show how human scientific intelligence might be limited
in certain respects, and introduces the core of Mysterianism, namely the
cognitive
closure. If Hume had been right, and the only concepts humans could
form were directly copied by the sensory input from the environment, then
the atomic theory would be cognitively closed to humankind, simply because
“you can’t see an atom” (p. 44). Now, McGinn argues, how do humans
really form concepts? Either by introspection, such as when I contemplate
my pain for a cut on my finger, or by “outer senses” e.g. smell and touch,
possibly with technological aids such as microscopes. Consciousness can
only be accessed through introspection, while the brain may only be investigated
through observations outward. It is thus the “irreducible duality in the
faculties through which we come to know” (p. 47) that fundamentally negates
the possibility of understanding how mind and brain go together.
Towards
the end of the second chapter it is noted that, unlike the brain, consciousness
might be quite simple after all. The author argues that the basic elements
of consciousness are possessed by many species, and that it is hard to
imagine that Evolution would have introduced a “complex” element all in
one step. The chapter ends with what can be considered a manifesto of Mysterianism:
ten points to explain why accepting that the mind-body relationship cannot
be understood is not a “depressingly negative conclusion”, but rather a
“palatable, even liberating” admission. These arguments are meant to suggest
a broader discussion on the attitude towards life, knowledge, faith, and
scientific investigation, and, the author emphasizes, should not be considered
in logical support of Mysterianism. This portion stands out from
the rest of the book, but it might have a great impact on philosophical
thought, should the mysterian theory be proven right. The main lines of
reasoning here are that knowing what we cannot know gives more power in
interpreting what we do know, and it prevents wasting time and energy which
could be used to study phenomena we may hope to understand; it helps demarcate
the line between the rational acceptance of a scientific mystery, and the
religious abandon to mystical and magical processes; knowledge is not necessarily
pleasant, science and technology have a dark side, and the sense of awe
is entertainingly fascinating; accepting your own limitation is noble and
elevating rather than depressing; and a new branch of science might emerge
from this position: can we modify (e.g., genetically) human beings so that
they could “come to grips with consciousness” (p.76)?
In
chapter three, other theories and positions about consciousness are considered.
The mysterian conclusion is compared to the assumption of the existence
of God, and to alternative variations of the dualistic view. More “outlandish”
theories of the mind-brain link, called panpsychism and mentalism
are introduced and criticized. The problems found in all these approaches,
according to McGinn, encourage a more ready acceptance of Mysterianism.
Chapter four is dedicated to discussion of the relationship between consciousness
and space, which is a great favorite of McGinn’s [22, 23]. The non-spatiality
of consciousness is troublesome, since classically, consciousness is seen
as a phenomenon emerging from physical processes, with spatial components
and spatial properties. McGinn argues that it seems reasonable to admit
that our concept of space is inadequate and lacking, and that we need a
radical breakthrough on this matter. However, he continues, no other concept
of space is available to us, and rightly so, considering the way we act
in space and the evolutionary path that led to our sensory modalities.
We are like Flatlanders, intrinsically unable to perceive one or
more dimensions of space, and therefore, to make sense of some phenomena
involving these extra dimensions. The conclusion, once again, is that we
are cognitively closed with respect to the true nature of space.
Chapter
five discusses a fine distinction between conscious and unconscious computation.
It is argued that there is a hidden structure of consciousness that
lies in between the surface of consciousness and the unconscious proper.
Two categorical examples are given for the hidden structure. The first
shows how common human logic makes use of hidden intermediate steps. In
order to understand the paradox “the queen of America is bald” one has
to accept the false premise of the existence of a queen of America. According
to McGinn, this implicit assumption, which is not apparent in the grammatically
correct sentence, is an example of the hidden structure of conscious thought.
The second example concerns blindsight, i.e. the ability of people with
lesions in specific brain areas to acquire visual knowledge while declaring
they cannot see anything. McGinn concludes that in normal vision too there
is a hidden component of conscious perception. Just as there is more to
an object than I can perceive (its atomic structure, for example), so there
is more to my visual experience than I can voluntarily reflect upon. The
author continues the argument by claiming that “we cannot know ourselves,
not all the way down.” (p.163). Letting go of this craving to explain,
it is concluded, leaves space for the existence of free will. The notion
of physical causality negates the possibility of making free decisions.
Our decisions are not behavioral reactions, but at the same time they are
not always superficially conscious either. They are “hidden”, and form
part of the mystery.
Chapter
six considers the possibility of conscious machines. As far as we know,
it is argued, simulation of behavior does not imply inner consciousness,
and the Turing test should be discarded as useless: animals are as sentient
of pain as we can be, yet they would fail the Turing test; a “complicated”
computer program could eventually pass the Turing test, yet it would
still remain an unconscious algorithm. Maybe, McGinn hypothesizes, for
a machine to be conscious we have to assume that it should be made out
of organic matter (consciousness has never seemed to emanate from an inorganic
source). And as far as how to build such a machine, this falls into
the mysterian realm, since we do not know what makes consciousness
emerge from the material world. No hard conclusion can be drawn at this
stage, but a wise dosage of skepticism is advised. The same can be said
about the inverse problem, i.e. whether or not there could exist a “smart”
animal, a well behaved organism, which had no inner consciousness nonetheless.
We do not know, and the chapter ends with this open question. Finally,
the last chapter proposes a new role for philosophers, in line with the
thesis offered in the Mysterious Flame: philosophers should delineate
the boundaries of intelligible knowledge, liberating Science from the burden
of mystery. Is all of what is usually termed “consciousness” really unintelligible?
Not quite: only the purely subjective “inner” component is. So, although
scientists should waste no time trying to understand the link between the
feeling
of pain and the electrophysiological activity of certain neuronal fibers,
a careful philosophical analysis might find the limits of what components
of pain, in terms of behavioral and intellectual knowledge, can be causally
related to brain activity.
Several
central arguments presented in McGinn’s book seem critically flawed, and
the result is poor logical support for the mysterian hypothesis. The first
problems concern the discussion of Materialism. Here, the story of Jackson’s
famous character Mary is retold, in order to show that the knowledge of
a physiological state does not imply the knowledge of mental states (see
also discussion in [16], and references therein). Mary is an imaginary,
bright and well-equipped neuroscientist, who was born and raised, and always
lived, in an artificially black-and white environment. She knows everything
about her brain activity and functioning, at the system, cellular, and
molecular level. However, she has never seen colored objects. Although
she knows how her nervous system reacts when the retina is stimulated with
electromagnetic waves, when she finally is allowed to see a red rose, she
has to admit that there was something missing in her knowledge, which is
the sensation of redness itself. One of the main problems with this argument
is that there is no evidence whatsoever that Mary would have a sensation
of redness, after she became adult in a black and white world. In fact,
there is evidence that the visual system of mammals is extremely plastic,
and, to a certain extent, adapts itself to perceive what the environment
has to offer [24]. It is highly conceivable that human infants gradually
learn
to perceive the sensation of redness only after several sensory exposures
to red objects. The only way Mary could really know everything about
her brain, including how it represents red light, would be to actually
have her retina stimulated with red light enough to allow the development
of normal neural connections.
A
similar argument used by McGinn in his critique of Materialism is borrowed
from Nagel’s discussion of “what it is like to be a bat”. Since humans
are not capable of echolocation, even if we understand the details of how
bat brains achieve it, we will not be able to imagine how it feels. From
the study of bat neurobiology, however, we might infer some qualitative
relationship between the auditory, visual, and echolocation senses. This
could, in principle, give us a rough idea of what an echolocation quale
feels like. There is some clinical evidence involving human patients who
lost their corneas to disease at around age 10 months. In adulthood, as
the technology for cornea transplants was developed, these subjects underwent
operations and acquired physiologically functioning eyes once again. Patients
who, before the operation, had been trained to imagine visual sensation
through touch and sound, were actually able to acquire a much more complete
visual perception than others [25].
Jackson’s
“Mary” and Nagel’s “bat” arguments lose much of their strength when analyzed
in light of a more subtle analysis of Materialism, that McGinn addresses
only tangentially, probably in order to leave his book more accessible
to the lay public. This analysis concerns the distinction between identity
and causal correlation. If we found, for instance, that a certain conscious
experience C occurs if and only if a certain neural pattern N
is present in the nervous system, could we conclude that the conscious
experience is that neural pattern? Or shall we rather maintain that
Ccauses
N? Patricia Churchland is in favor of the identity hypothesis, and
compares this scenario to other similar debates that accompanied previous
scientific revolutions [26]. It is not that particle motion causes
temperature. Particle motion is temperature, as strange as it may
seem. It is not that the movement of electrons causes electricity.
Movement of electrons is electricity, as strange as it may seem,
and so forth. When we find what are the elements of neural patterns
that correspond to conscious experience, we will get used to the
idea of an identity, just because any other explanation would be too complicated:
the mystery will vanish. In criticizing Materialism, Churchland claims,
McGinn makes an unwarranted leap from “it is unimaginable” to “it is impossible”,
and the logical gap between the two statements is usually filled with “dust
which cloaks the fallacious core of the argument” [26].
The
alternative position would argue that, unlike temperature and electricity,
consciousness might be caused by brain states though not identical
with them, given the objective/subjective gap that divides the two concepts
[27]. Interestingly, in a now famous keynote paper, Chalmers admits the
gap between C and N (what he calls the Hard Problem),
and yet refuses to embrace McGinn’s Mysterianism [28]. In accusing the
mysterian position of excessive pessimism, Chalmers believes that this
is no place to give up, it is the place, rather, where things become interesting.
Even if we are open to the possibility that reductive explanations fail
to satisfy our curiosity about consciousness, he claims, the nonreductive
approach needs to be explored. Chalmers’ ideas, and the subsequent discussions
[29], constitute an extremely important alternative view to radical Materialism.
This subject is inexplicably overlooked in the Mysterious Flame,
and it deserves commentary here in that it seriously challenges the novelty
and the depth of Mysterianism [17, 28]. Chalmers notes that it occasionally
happens, in physics, that an entity is to be taken as fundamental.
Most phenomena can be explained in terms of something simpler (such as
electricity and temperature, mentioned above), but this is by no means
universal. Examples of fundamental entities are charge, mass, or space-time.
Regarding the aforementioned example of electricity, why is it that
electrons are negatively charged, why is it that there should be
such a property as charge at all, apparently with two states (positive
and negative), and why is it that negatively and positively charged
objects should attract each other, while objects with the same charge tend
to repel each other? Similar fundamental questions can be formulated for
mass and gravitation. Questions can become even more precise: why is the
gravitation constant exactly what it is, and not, say, twice that amount?
When
it turned out that electromagnetic processes could not be explained in
terms of classical mechanics, Chalmers argues, scientists introduced novel
fundamental components in the physical theory, including properties (charge)
and laws that went with them. The ontology of physics itself underwent
an expansion. This process lasted for decades and eventually led to the
explanation of apparently uncorrelated macroscopic phenomena such as ferromagnetism.
Similarly, according to Chalmers, a complete theory of consciousness will
have to introduce some new fundamental properties. In order to delineate
these properties, however, and the laws that coordinate them, we need to
learn more about the branches of science related to conscious experience,
namely neuroscience and behavioral psychology. The more we learn about
the “easy” problem, the more we will be able to narrow in and nail down
the characteristics of the entities to be eventually assumed as fundamental.
What
earlier physicists (mainly Galileo and Newton) did with mechanics was to
recognize that many phenomena could be described in terms of a restricted
number of laws and parameters. It was this process that led to the assumption
of mass as a fundamental entity. What is Mysterianism really? If it were
the admission that fundamental properties cannot be explained further,
then it would be no novelty. But in The Mysterious Flame, the whole
subject surrounding consciousness is regarded as a deep mystery, and in
fact, there is no deep reason to do so. Even if we assume that there
is something “mysterious” (or, perhaps better, “fundamental”) in the
process of consciousness, then it would be important to carve out all we
can describe quantitatively about the process, so as to leave a minimum
set of equations and parameters. In order to do that, we need to study
and describe which C corresponds to which N and vice versa.
If we knew the neural correlates of consciousness, if we knew which properties
of neural patterns correspond to elements of conscious experience, then
we could outline a theory, inclusive of fundamental properties and laws,
coherent with this knowledge. In his keynote article, Chalmers proposes
a series of lucid programmatic steps to reach this point from the current
status of neurobiology and experimental psychology. His main principles,
namely structural coherence, organizational invariance, and
the double-aspect theory of information [28], address several of
the issues McGinn raises in The Mysterious Flame, and it is surprising
that they are ignored in this book.
Chalmers’
analysis of the process leading to scientific theories can be reformulated
in terms of quantitative equations describing the laws of nature. For example,
Copernicus’ and Galileo’s observations on the motion of bodies were summarized
in the two equations
F
= G * m1 * m2 * d -2(2)
where
F
is the (gravitational) force between two bodies of mass m1
and m2 separated by a distance d, and G
is a (universal) constant. Experimental observations suggest that the mass
referred to in equation 1 is actually the very same property as the mass
referred to in equation 2, although there is no logical reason for
it to be so. So, we assume that there is one fundamental entity
of physical bodies called mass, and not two (inertial and gravitational)#.
One can derive Copernicus’ laws from equations 1 and 2, and therefore Copernicus’
laws are usually not regarded as fundamental. There is an implicit principle
of minimization of the fundamental equations here: natural theories should
keep the number of fundamental equations (and also, fundamental parameters
and universal constants) to a minimum##.
For example, a great revolution in thermodynamics was achieved when equations
such as
P
* V = N * K * T(3)
(where
P is the pressure of a gas, V its volume, N the number of
its molecules, K a (universal) constant, and T the temperature)
could be explained in terms of equation 1 by assuming a statistical definition
of P and T in terms of molecular mass and velocity [30].
The debate between radical Materialism (C is N) and
Chalmers’ position (Ccauses N, and we have to understand
how), can be restated as an argument about whether consciousness can be
explained in terms of the presently accepted fundamental laws of physics,
or whether we need additional fundamental laws. In either case, it is necessary
to define and describe quantitatively both C and N before
reaching a conclusion. From this perspective, Mysterianism looks like an
unjustified third route.
The
fact is, at this stage of neuroscience knowledge, we simply do not know
enough to establish what the neural correlates of qualia are. The first
chapter of The Mysterious Flame has a title that encapsulates one
of the ideas encouraging Mysterianism: “Still unexplained after all these
years”. It is true that the nature of consciousness has evaded philosophers’
grasp for thousands of years. But if we want to give neurobiology a chance,
we must admit that we are just at the beginning. Are certain patterns of
“neuronal activity” all there is to consciousness? We cannot give
an answer, not necessarily because the question is cognitively closed to
us, but because we have not learned enough about what the characteristics
of those neural patterns must be. From this perspective, Materialism might
be wrong, but equally, it might very well be true. As Churchland pointed
out, it seems unreasonably early to give up on the attempt to find out
how the brain performs its job: as long as experiments continue to produce
results that so greatly advance our understanding, why not keep going [26]?
Science
proceeds by collecting observations, and by connecting them to previously
established laws (possibly at different scales or explanatory levels),
or by establishing novel laws to accommodate them. In a way, it is the
set of fundamental laws, parameters, and universal constants, that constitute
the limit and the boundary of human knowledge. Is McGinn’s call for a unique
role for philosophers in this process meaningful? Unfortunately, The
Mysterious Flame leaves this entire body of questions regarding the
ontology of science untouched.
The
lack of discussion of Churchland and Chalmers’ claim that we do not know
enough neurobiology yet to (dis)prove Materialism and/or to discover the
fundamental entities that describe consciousness scientifically, constitutes
the crucial flaw of The Mysterious Flame, and of Mysterianism in
general. This same issue emerges, in one form or another, in several parts
of the book. For example, in the core discussion in favor of the cognitive
closure of the brain-consciousness relationship (pp. 49-53), McGinn argues
as follows: “There is some property of the brain, let’s call it C*, that
explains how consciousness emerges from neural tissue. […] If we look hard
enough inside the crevices of the cortex, we will eventually come across
the property C*. […] But this is pure fantasy. The key point here is that
just as consciousness itself is not, as a matter of principle, visible
in the brain, so C* - which constitutes the very essence of consciousness
– is not visible either. […] To understand the general theory of consciousness
we would need to understand how the specific forms of consciousness arise
from particular sorts of brain property. But that would require us to be
able to form concepts of types of experience we cannot in fact conceive.”
In reviewing this passage, it is apparent how the key problem is not even
stated: either C* actually explains consciousness in terms of other
physical laws (much like the statistical interpretation of gas dynamics
explains the relationship among temperature, pressure, and volume in terms
of particle number and movement) or C* constitutes a radically new set
of physical entities and laws (much like electrical charge had to be introduced
in order to explain electromagnetism). McGinn has no satisfying reason
why we should not be able to see C* as long as we define it as “the
neural correlate of consciousness” rather than “the property that explains
how consciousness emerges from the neural tissue”.
In
another crucial passage of chapter 2, one reads “Can we take the atoms
of the brain (neurons and their parts) and combine them according to appropriate
laws into conscious states? The answer is clearly ‘No’. When you have an
experience of yellow, your conscious state does indeed depend for its existence
upon what is happening in your neurons in the visual area of your cortex.
But it is not true that your experience has such neural processes as its
constituents.
It is not made up of the processes that constitute its neural correlate.
The conscious state does not have an internal structure that is defined
by its physical underpinning. […] The kind of neural complexity that lies
behind a conscious experience does not show up in its phenomenological
character. Neurons are not the atoms from which consciousness is composed
by means of lawlike combinations.” Again, there is a misconception here
of what counts as an explanation. We accept the atomic theory in physics,
even if not all the properties of a substance can be directly inferred
by its atomic constituents. In fact, substances made up of identical atomic
units are well known to chemists to have quite different properties, depending
on how the atoms are arranged in the molecule. So, the hardness of diamond,
the liquidity of water, and the viscosity of oil, are emergent properties
of their constituents. In the end, it is possible to rationalize the properties
of diamond, water, and oil, based on those of carbon, hydrogen, and oxygen,
and thanks to our understanding of quantum and classical mechanics and
electromagnetism. But it takes many logical steps to connect (extract)
emergent properties of matter to (from) the atomic components. If we knew
as little about the chemical elements as we know about neuronal processes,
the emergent physical properties of substances would look quite mysterious
even to the most careful observer. However, after the properties of the
atomic constituents were finally understood, the whole macroscopic picture
made sense altogether.
The
above example is not the only source of confusion of what would count as
a solution to the mind-body problem according to McGinn. In an early paragraph
of the book, the molecular analogy is actually presented (p. 20): “all
the facts about water are facts about H2O, although the words
‘water’ and ‘H2O’ do not mean the same thing: they are not synonyms.”
One of the main theses of Mysterianism is that mind cannot be explained
from brain like water from H2O. However, towards the end of
the book, the author outlines what we really need in order to explain the
relationship between brain and consciousness (p. 217): “We can know, that
is, that radically new concepts are necessary and that they would have
to be connected to each other rather in the way that ‘bachelor’ is connected
to ‘unmarried male’. […] If I am right, we are not going to come up with
that solution”. The major flaw here is that the definition of bachelor
contains the meaning of unmarried male. One can understand the logical
relationship between the properties of water and H2O without
having to define one concept with the other. Again, a deeper discussion
of identity and causal relation in physical laws would have helped clarify
what is acceptable as “knowledge” about consciousness, and whether Mysterianism
is really a necessity, or just a possibility.
Similarly,
when the appearance of consciousness in evolution is discussed in The
Mysterious Flame, the possibility that consciousness is a truly emergent
property is not considered. McGinn writes (p. 63): “I like to imagine that
day, many millions of years ago, when the first sentient organism came
along, and a brand new ingredient entered the cosmos. […] It was early,
primitive, and not especially smart. It almost seems as if evolution could
not help producing consciousness once it discovered sensory processes.
I therefore see no reason to believe that consciousness is any more ‘complex’
or ‘advanced’ than digestion or sexual reproduction.” McGinn’s belief here
has no real scientific basis. In fact, many primitive organisms are known
to lack a nervous system (which by the author’s own admission seems to
be an essential substrate of consciousness), yet are able to digest and
sexually reproduce. They can “sense” by means of chemoreceptors, but how
can we possibly know that they have “consciousness”, if consciousness is
defined as “the having of sensation, emotions, feelings, thought” (p. 2)?
And if a saturated/unsaturated chemoreceptor is our threshold to admit
“sensation”, then why should microchips not be sentient, or thermometers,
or gas gauges? The subject of the appearance of consciousness in evolution
is harder (and more meaningful) to discuss if we consider the emergent
properties of information representation in nervous systems. This
cannot be done until the neural correlates of consciousness are scientifically
pinned down.
Unfortunately,
questions such as “What is the minimum complexity a representing system
needs to have in order to allow a process such as consciousness?” are simply
rejected in The Mysterious Flame: “The deeper question here is how
a bunch of cells can become a self anyway: What converts biological
tissue into that self whose existence so impressed Decartes? The fact is
that there are no scientific criteria for the appearance of selves; all
we have are shaky intuitions […]. Maybe, then, we cannot know ourselves,
not all the way down. We can know we exist all right, but we cannot grasp
our intrinsic nature” (p. 162). In this conviction, however, McGinn is
neglecting many discussions in the scientific literature insisting on a
role for complexity in the explanation of consciousness (see e.g. [31-32]
among many examples). Given the title of the journal this essay is meant
for, I cannot help but quote a passage from the very beginning of the book
(p. 11): “Some people like to harp on the complexity of the brain, as if
this gave a clue to its mental productivity. But sheer complexity is irrelevant:
merely adding more neurons with more synaptic connections doesn’t explain
our problem a bit. […] The trouble is that neural complexity is the wrong
kind
of thing to explain consciousness. It is merely a matter of how many cells
a given cell can causally interact with.” Clearly, the author’s excessive
simplification of the concepts of information and complex systems, prevents
him from appreciating another possible perspective in the discussion of
consciousness.
Much
in the same way, the progress concerning adaptive neural networks, evolutionary
algorithms, and computer models of brain portions is neglected in the discussion
of the (im)possibility of conscious computers (p. 184-185): “The computer
merely uses electronic pulses to rearrange its internal states; nothing
in this implies that it is conscious. There is no more reason to believe
a computer is conscious than a table is. […] A computer is a high-tech
puppet: you pull the strings and watch it respond, but it no more has a
mind than Punch and Judy do. And making it more complex is not going to
alter its basic character. If symbol manipulations do not produce consciousness
in simpler cases, why should adding more of them make any difference?”
Again, it is unclear why McGinn does not recognize at this point the possibility
for complex macrophenomena to emerge from simple microsystems. A single
moving molecule does not “produce” temperature, or liquidity, why should
adding more of them make any difference? And similarly, how can we explain
the chaotic pattern of traffic from the characteristic of a single automobile?
The
same superficiality of argument is apparent in the initial discussion of
what self-awareness is (p. 3): McGinn only describes higher order states,
particularly the ability to reflect on one’s own experience and to characterize
oneself as conscious. The Mysterious Flame, it is said, is about
the fact of consciousness, not its self-ascription. The author claims:
“Many animals are in the same state: they have a conscious life, but they
do not aspire to reflect on this fact. They do not, to put it another way,
apply mental concepts to themselves. To have a conscious state is
not the same as applying a concept of that conscious state to oneself,
any more than to have a certain color hair is to describe oneself
as having that color hair.” Here there seems to be a certain confusion
about the formation of the concept of Self (for a more detailed discussion
on this subject, see [33]), and about the relationship between this process
and the ability to ascribe mental states to oneself. In fact, one could
argue that self-consciousness is not equivalent to having a concept of
self, any more than feeling pain is the same as having an abstract concept
of pain. At this stage, it would have been extremely important to discuss
the possibility that phenomenological consciousness, or qualia, are only
possible when self-awareness is present [13, 33]. Again, several subsequent
arguments
in support of Mysterianism lose strength in light of this omission.
The
possibility of creating artificial consciousness, discussed at the end
of the book, represents the natural setup for a thought experiment with
interesting consequences for Materialism and Mysterianism. McGinn chooses
not to take this opportunity and to conclude that we cannot know whether
or not artificial consciousness is a possibility. So, let us take up the
discussion from where The Mysterious Flame leaves off. Since the
mechanism by which single neurons function appears to be relatively understandable
and to fall within the realm of “objective” science, we may think of creating
artificial neurons, either physically in a microchip, or virtually in software.
If neurons were believed to be too mysterious for this operation, we might
in principle even start from sub-cellular components, such as dendritic
branches and spines, axonal shafts and varicosities, somatic organelles,
and neurotransmitter vesicles. If it were proven that quantum phenomena
played a key role in the function of these components, we could implement
or build the basic units with stochastic rules to reflect this fact. Of
course, we would need various types of artificial neurons for the different
classes of neurons present in the nervous system. If we had a precise map
of all the input/output connections of a person’s brain at any time, we
could start substituting one by one each neuron of his/her nervous system
with an artificial analogue, until the whole subject’s brain would be replaced,
essentially, by an artificial machine. Although, at the present stage of
knowledge, this is just a thought experiment, we may nonetheless start
asking questions: would the subject retain consciousness, or at which point
in the process would (s)he start (and finish) losing it? It is unreasonable
to state that this question will forever remain a mystery, because, in
principle, there is no reason technology will not reach this goal sometime
in the future. The thesis defended in The Mysterious Flame would
be consistent with the position that the “artificialized” person would
still be conscious, but we would still know nothing of the relationship
between his/her consciousness and the ensemble of our chips (or virtual
neuron-like algorithms). Let us then imagine carrying out the same operation
of “brain artificialization” on a second individual. In principle, if we
assume that the sensation of red (given the sight of the same red object)
is similar or identical for the two individuals, we may map the “neural”
state of one brain-machine to that of the other. For this purpose, it is
not necessary for the two neural states to be identical. In fact, given
the different individual histories of the two subjects, we would expect
that the neural states corresponding to “identical” sensations should be
somewhat different. (Incidentally, by studying the general analogies among
the neural states of many such brain-machines in correspondence to a certain
quale, we could find the neural correlate of that quale.)
Perhaps
before the simulation of an entire human brain, scientific progress will
allow the simulation of a “virtual life”, which is the entire set of sensory
inputs received by a human being in a life span (counting 10 images per
second for a 600×600 pixel retina at 32-bit resolution, this would
sum up to roughly 30 million GB of data, before compression, for 70 years
of visual modality). Then we can imagine connecting the brain-machine individuals
to the virtual life simulator. Naturally, the life simulator will have
to be plastic, to adapt its outcome (that is, the sensory inputs to the
brain-machine) to the behavior of the individual. The “behavior” of the
individual, needless to say, might be purely virtual if we wish to disconnect
the subject’s body from his/her brain machine. At that point, the individual
will be living a purely virtual input/output existence. Needless to say,
brain-machine would be plastic too (i.e. they would change their structure
and properties through the interaction with the life simulator), because
they represent accurate models of real brains. The advantage of this setup
is that now all the variables of our thought experiment are completely
controlled. That is, we can reasonably administer the very same input (or
history of inputs) to each individual, and we can expect to elicit the
same or similar conscious experience (in principle, this could only be
true if brains were hooked up to the life simulator when the individual
was born, but this detail does not really affect the thought experiment).
At this stage, we may map the neural correlates of any conscious experience
for each individual. Not only can we then control the individual conscious
experience (by tuning the life simulator) and then monitor the neural correlate
in the brain machine; we can also impose a specific neural pattern (by
tuning the brain machine) and record the conscious outcome as a behavioral
correlate in the life simulator. An even more extreme situation can be
designed: we can have the “scientist” and the “experimental subject” both
hooked up to brain machines and life-simulators. The scientist will be
able to study the neural patterns of the subject and also experience personally
his/her corresponding introspective states, by “replaying” the corresponding
patterns on his/her own setup. This thought experiment shows that, if we
believe that conscious experience is somehow exclusively related to brain
activity (i.e. it emerges from brain activity, it is caused
by brain activity, or simply is brain activity), which is not inconsistent
with McGinn’s position, there seems to be no reason, in principle, that
one could not study the relationship between the two aspects (qualia and
neural correlates) both introspectively and objectively. This would lead
in turn to answering many open questions in the philosophy of consciousness
and in neurobiology, and would likely disclose the additional (if any)
fundamental physical entities and laws necessary to describe consciousness
scientifically.
An
almost independent part of The Mysterious Flame deals with
the “advantages” of Mysterianism mentioned above. Among these are the benefits
that individuals can receive from recognizing their intellectual limitation
and the enjoyment of a humble awe for Nature. This discussion is concentrated
at the end of the second chapter (pp. 69-76) and several themes are then
developed in later chapters. Particularly, McGinn suggests that Mysterianism,
by rejecting the possibility that we will ever subsume consciousness to
our understanding of determinism and causation, allows the possibility
of free will (p. 168). And he illustrates how cognitive closure might relieve
the fear of death, or at least how further knowledge about death could
elicit even more unpleasant emotions (pp. 169-171). Aside from the statement
that scientific progress comes with a dark side (nuclear weapons, pollution,
excessive experimentation on humans), this discussion seems too personal
to be analyzed at an objective level. Some readers will undoubtedly appreciate
it, while others will probably find it inappropriate. Suffice it to say
that some of the same “advantages” could in principle be obtained without
embracing a mysterian position. The assumption that one day consciousness
will be described and explained by physical laws still leaves space for
awe in the contemplation of why there is matter, and why fundamental physical
laws are the way they are (no matter what the mind is, never mind what
matter is).
A
last word needs to be said about the bibliography of
The Mysterious
Flame. From a book intended for the lay public, one would expect to
be provided with an objective review of accessible works on the subject,
i.e. both in favor and against the main thesis. In addition, when critical
passages are only discussed superficially to allow easier and readier comprehension,
all appropriate sources should be cited. McGinn exhaustively refers to
his previous work, and only rarely quotes appropriate alternative views
in the literature. A modern philosophical discussion of consciousness cannot
be sustained without taking into consideration basic neuroscientific evidence,
and this is completely lacking in The Mysterious Flame’s bibliography.
In contrast, other recent books on the subject point readers to a valuable
collection of publications with which they can continue their intellectual
journey: the most striking case is Metzinger and Chalmers’ effort [34],
but other examples include [35] and, for a completely non-technical book,
[36].
To
summarize, Colin McGinn’s The Mysterious Flame – Conscious Mind in a
Material World is an accessible, well written book, containing a number
of stimulating and provocative ideas and a radical central thesis. The
overall impression it leaves the reader with is that “maybe” we will not
understand what consciousness is in the end. However, many logical arguments
presented in the book are simply not convincing. In particular, the discussion
of Materialism and emergent phenomena is never brought to the relevant
level of the ontology of science. The resulting conclusion we draw is that,
quite positively, it is not yet time to give up on a science of consciousness.
Acknowledgments:I
am indebted to Drs. Joe Grady and Rebecca Goldin for reviewing and commenting
on the manuscript, to Dr. Paolo Biscari for several ideas on the subject,
and to Drs. Jim Olds and Harold Morowitz for continuous support and encouragement.
2.J.J.
Hopfield: Pattern recognition computation using action potential timing
for stimulus representation. Nature 376(6535): pp. 33-36, 1995.
3.T.J.
Gawne: Temporal coding as a means of information transfer in the primate
visual system. Crit. Rev. Neurobiol. 13(1): pp. 83-101, 1999.
4.J.J.
Eggermont: Is there a neural code? Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 22(2): pp.
355-370, 1998.
5.W.M.
Usrey, R.C. Reid: Synchronous activity in the visual system. Annu. Rev.
Physiol. 61: pp. 435-456, 1999.
6.E.A.
Maguire, N. Burgess, J. O'Keefe: Human spatial navigation: cognitive maps,
sexual dimorphism, and neural substrates. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 9(2):
pp. 171-177, 1999.
7.M.
Iacoboni, J.C. Baron, R.S. Frackowiak, J.C. Mazziotta, G.L. Lenzi: Emission
tomography contribution to clinical neurology. Clin. Neurophysiol. 110(1):
pp. 2-23, 1999.
8.M.
Reite, P. Teale, D.C. Rojas: Magnetoencephalography: applications in psychiatry.
Biol. Psychiatry 45(12): pp. 1553-1563, 1999.
9.G.M.
Edelman: The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness.
New York: Basic Books, 1989.
10.D.C.
Dennet: Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1991.
11.D.M.
Rosenthal: A theory of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, G. Guzeldere
(eds.): The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996.
12.F.H.C.
Crick: The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribner’s Sons, 1994.
13.A.R.
Damasio: Descartes’ Error. New York: Putnam, 1994.
14.R.
Llinas, U. Ribary, D. Contreras, C. Pedroarena: The neuronal basis for
consciousness. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 353(1377): pp.
1841-1849, 1998.
15.R.
Penrose: The Emperor’s New Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989.
16.M.
Nida-Rumelin: What Mary couldn’t know: belief about phenomenal states.
In T. Metzinger: Conscious Experience. Thoverton: Imprint Academic, 1995.
17.D.J.
Chalmers: The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
18.C.
McGinn: The Problem of Consciousness. Oxford: Basic Blackwell, 1991.
19.C.
McGinn: Problems in Philosophy. Oxford: Basic Blackwell, 1993.
20.C.
McGinn: The Character of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.
21.C.
McGinn: Minds and Bodies. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997.
22.C.
McGinn: Consciousness and space. J. Consciousness Studies 2(3): pp. 220-230,
1995.
23.C.
McGinn: Consciousness and space. In T. Metzinger: Conscious Experience.
Thoverton: Imprint Academic, 1995.
24.M.P.
Stryker, B. Chapman, K.D. Miller, K.R. Zahs: Experimental and theoretical
studies of the organization of afferents to single orientation columns
in visual cortex. Cold Spring Harb. Symp. Quant. Biol. 55: pp. 515-527,
1990.
25.R.L.
Gregory: Knowledge in perception and illusion. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond.
B Biol. Sci. 352(1358): pp. 1121-1127, 1997.
26.P.S. Churchland: Can neurobiology teach us anything about consciousness? In H.J. Morowitz, J.L. Singer (eds.): The Mind, the Brain, and Complex Adaptive Systems. Santa Fe Inst. Proc. Sci. Complexity 22: pp. 99-121, Reading: Addison-Wesley, 1995. Based on a presidential address reported in Proc. Addresses APA, 1994. Also available at http://cogsci.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Papers/Py104/church.neuro.html
27.J.R.
Searle: The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992.
28.D.J.
Chalmers: Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J. Consciousness Studies
2(3): pp. 200-219, 1995.
29.J.
Shear: Explaining Consciousness – The Hard Problem. Special issue with
contributions. J. Consciousness Studies 3(1), 1996.
30.A.J.
Ihde: The Development of Modern Chemistry. New York: Dover, 1984.
31.V.G.
Hardcastle: Psychology’s binding problem and possible neurobiological solutions.
J. Consciousness Studies 1(1): pp. 66-90, 1994.
32.G.
Tononi, G.M. Edelman: Consciousness and complexity. Science 282(5395):
pp. 1846-1851, 1998.
33.G.A.
Ascoli: Association, abstraction, and the emergence of the Self. Noetic
J. 2(1): pp. 9-20, 1999.
34.T.
Metzinger, D.J. Chalmers: Consciousness in philosophy, cognitive science,
and neuroscience 1970-1995. In T. Metzinger: Conscious Experience. Thoverton:
Imprint Academic, 1995. This collection is also available (and constantly
updated) at
http://ling.ucsc.edu/~chalmers/mind.html
35.P.S.
Churchland, T.J. Sejnowski: The Computational Brain. Cambridge: MIT Press,
1992.
36.D.L.
Alkon: Memory’s Voice – Deciphering the Min-Brain Code. New York: HarperCollins,
1992.